logo

drewdevault.com

[mirror] blog and personal website of Drew DeVault git clone https://hacktivis.me/git/mirror/drewdevault.com.git
commit: 1576bb06fa339463ecaa591810477be246e0c9ec
parent e548b56453be988cbf3186639f8c19d67edf04d6
Author: Drew DeVault <sir@cmpwn.com>
Date:   Fri, 14 Feb 2025 11:12:22 +0100

A holistic perspective on intellectual property, part 1

Diffstat:

Acontent/blog/2025-02-13-On-intellectual-property.md245+++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
1 file changed, 245 insertions(+), 0 deletions(-)

diff --git a/content/blog/2025-02-13-On-intellectual-property.md b/content/blog/2025-02-13-On-intellectual-property.md @@ -0,0 +1,245 @@ +--- +title: A holistic perspective on intellectual property, part 1 +date: 2025-02-13 +--- + +I'd like to write about intellectual property in depth, in this first of a +series of blog posts on the subject. I'm not a philosopher, but philosophy is +the basis of reasonable politics so buckle up for a healthy Friday afternoon +serving of it. + +To understand intellectual property, we must first establish at least a shallow +understanding of property generally. What is property?[^note] An incomplete +answer might state that a material object I have power over is my property. An +apple I have held in my hand is mine, insofar as nothing prevents me from using +it (and, in the process, destroying it), or giving it away, or planting it in +the ground. However, you might not agree that this apple is necessarily *mine* +if I took it from a fruit stand without permission. This act is called "theft" +--- one of many possible transgressions upon property. + +[^note]: In today's article I will focus mainly on personal property (e.g. your + shoes), private property (e.g. a house or a business), and intellectual + property (e.g. a patent or a copyright). There are other kinds: public + property, collective property, and so on, but to simplify this article we + will use the layman's understanding of "property" as commonly referring to + personal property or private property, whichever is best supported by + context, unless otherwise specified. In general terms all of these kinds of + property refer to the rules with which society governs the use of *things*. + +It is important to note that the very possibility that one could illicitly +assume possession of an object is a strong indication that "property" is a +social convention, rather than a natural law; one cannot defy the law of gravity +in the same way as one can defy property. And, given that, we could try to +imagine other social conventions to govern the use of *things* in a society. If +we come up with an idea we like, and we're in a radical mood, we could even +challenge the notion of property in society at large and seek to implement a +different social convention. + +As it stands today, the social convention tells us property is a *thing* which +has an "owner", or owners, to whom society confers certain rights with respect +to the thing in question. That may include, for example, the right to use it, to +destroy it, to exclude others from using it, to sell it, or give it away, and so +on. Property is this special idea society uses to grant you the authority to use +a bunch of verbs with respect to a thing. However, being a social convention +rather than a natural law, nothing prevents me from using any of these verbs on +something society does not recognize as my property, e.g. by +<abbr title='"I have a bridge to sell you" is an English-language idiom that refers to selling something you do not own to a gullible person.'> +selling you this bridge</abbr>. This is why the social convention must be +**enforced**. + +And how is it enforced? We could enforce property rights with shame: stealing +can put a stain on one's reputation, and this shame may pose an impediment to +one's social needs and desires, and as such theft is discouraged. We can also +use guilt: if you steal something, but don't get caught, you could end up +remorseful without anyone to shame you for it, particularly with respect to the +harm done to the person who suffered a loss of property as a result. Ultimately, +in modern society the social convention of property is enforced with, well, +force. If you steal something, society has appointed someone with a gun to track +you down, restrain you, and eventually lock you up in a miserable room with bars +on the windows. + +--- + +*I'd like to take a moment here to acknowledge the hubris of property: we see the +bounty of the natural world and impose upon it these imagined rights and +privileges, divvy it up and hand it out and hoard it, and resort to cruelty if +anyone steps out of line. Indeed this may be justifiable if the system of +private property is sufficiently beneficial to society, and the notion of +property is so deeply ingrained into our system that it feels normal and +unremarkable. It's worth remembering that it has trade-offs, that we made the +whole thing up, and that we can make up something else with different +trade-offs. That being said, I'm personally fond of most of my personal property +and I'd like to keep enjoying most of my property rights as such, so take from +that what you will.*[^marx] + +[^marx]: Marx, among others, distinguishes between personal property and private + property. The distinction is drawn in that personal property can be moved -- + you can pick up a T-Shirt and take it somewhere else. Private property + cannot, such as land or a house. Anyway, I'm not a Marxist but I do draw + from Marxist ideas for some of my analysis of intellectual property, such as + the labor theory of value. We'll talk more about these ideas later on. + +--- + +One way we can justify property rights by using them as a tool for managing +*scarcity*. If demand for coffee exceeds the supply of coffee beans, a scarcity +exists, meaning that not everyone who wants to have coffee gets to have some. +But, we still want to enjoy scarce things. Perhaps someone who foregoes coffee +will enjoy some other scarce resource, such as tea --- then everyone can benefit +in some part from some access to scarce resources. I suppose that the social +convention of property can derive some natural legitimacy from the fact that +some resources are scarce.[^colonialism] In this sense, private property relates +to the problem of distribution. + +[^colonialism]: It occurred to me after writing this section that the selected + examples of property and scarcity as applied to coffee and tea are begging + for an analysis of the subject through the lens of colonialism, but I think + my readers are not quite ready for that yet. + +But a naive solution to distribution has flaws. For example, what of hoarding? +Are property rights legitimate when someone takes more than they need or intend +to use? This behavior could be motivated by an antagonistic relationship with +society at large, such as as a means of driving up prices for private profit; +such behavior could be considered anti-social and thus a violation of the social +convention as such. + +Moreover, property which is destroyed by its use, such as coffee, is one matter, +but further questions are raised when we consider durable goods, such as a +screwdriver. The screwdriver in my shed spends the vast majority of its time out +of use. Is it just for me to assert property rights over my screwdriver when I +am not using it? To what extent is the scarcity of screwdrivers *necessary*? +Screwdrivers are not fundamentally scarce, given that the supply of idle +screwdrivers far outpaces the demand for screwdriver use, but our modern +conception of property has the unintended consequence of creating scarcity where +there is none by denying the use of idle screwdrivers where they are needed. + +Let's try to generalize our understanding of property, working our way towards +"intellectual property" one step at a time. To begin with, what happens if we +expand our understanding of property to include immaterial things? Consider +domain names as a kind of property. In theory, domain names are abundant, but +some names are more desirable than others. We assert property rights over them, +in particular the right to use a name and exclude others from using it, or to +derive a profit from exclusive use of a desirable name. + +But a domain name doesn't really exist per-se: it's just an entry in a ledger. +The electric charge on the hard drives in your nearest DNS server's database +exist, but the domain name it represents doesn't exist in quite the same sense +as the electrons do: it's immaterial. Is applying our conception of property to +these immaterial things justifiable? + +We can start answering this question by acknowledging that property rights are +*useful* for domain names, in that this gives domain names desirable properties +that serve productive ends in society. For example, exclusive control over a +domain name allows a sense of authenticity to emerge from its use, so that you +understand that pointing your browser to drewdevault.com will return the content +that the person, Drew DeVault, wrote for you. We should also acknowledge that +there are negative side-effects of asserting property rights over domains, such +as domain squatting, extortionate pricing for "premium" domain names, and the +advantage one party has over another if they possess a desirable name by mere +fact of that possession, irrespective of merit. + +On the balance of things, if we concede the legitimacy of personal +property[^property legitimacy] I find it relatively easy to concede the +legitimacy of this sort of property, too. + +[^property legitimacy]: Not that I do, at least not entirely. I personally + envision a system in which wealth is capped, hoarding is illegal, and + everyone has an unconditional right to food, shelter, healthcare, and so on, + and I'll support reforming property rights in a heartbeat if that's what it + takes to get all of those things done. And, as the saying goes: if you see + someone stealing groceries, you didn't see anything. My willingness to + accept property as a legitimate social convention is conditional on it not + producing antisocial outcomes like homelessness or food insecurity. A system + like this is considered a form of "distributive justice", if you want to + learn more. + +The next step is to consider if we can generalize property rights to govern +immaterial, non-finite things, like a story. A book, its paper and bindings and +ink, is a material, finite resource, and can be thought of in terms that apply +to material property. But what of the words formed by the ink? They can be +trivially copied with a pen and paper, or transformed into a new medium by +reading it aloud to an audience, and these processes do not infringe on the +material property rights associated with the book. This process cannot be +thought of as stealing, as the person who possesses a copy of the book is not +asserting property rights over the original. In our current intellectual +property regime, this person is transgressing via use of the *idea*, the +*intellectual* property --- the *thing* in the abstract space occupied by the +story itself. Is that, too, a just extension of our notion of property? + +Imagine with me the relationship one has with one's property, independent of the +social constructs around property. With respect to material property, a +relationship of possession exists: I physically possess a thing, and I have the +ability to make use of it through my possession of it. If someone else were to +deny me access to this thing, they would have to resort to force, and I would +have to resort to force should I resist their efforts. + +Our relationship with intellectual property is much different. An idea cannot be +withheld or seized by force. Instead, our relationship to intellectual property +is defined by our *history* with respect to an idea. In the case of material +property, the ground truth is that I keep it locked in my home to deny others +access to it, and the social construct formalizes this relationship. With +respect to intellectual property, such as the story in a book, the ground truth +is that, sometime in the past, I imagined it and wrote it down. The social +construct of intellectual property invents an imagined relationship of +possession, modelled after our relationship with material property. + +Why? + +The resource with the greatest and most fundamental scarcity is our time,[^time] +and as a consequence the labor which goes into making something is of profound +importance. Marx famously argued for a "labor theory of value", which tells us +that the value inherent in a good or service is in the labor which is required +to provide it. I think he was on to something![^marx 2] Intellectual property is +not scarce, nor can it be possessed, but it does have *value*, and that value +could ultimately be derived from the labor which produced it. + +[^time]: And you're spending some of it to read my silly blog, which I really + feel is an honor. Thank you. +[^marx 2]: Marx loses me at historical determinism and the dominance of man over + nature through dogmatic industrialization, among other things, but the labor + theory of value is good shit. + +The social justification for intellectual property as a legal concept is rooted +in the value of this labor. We recognize that intellectual labor is valuable, +and produces an artifact --- e.g. a story --- which is valuable, but is not +scarce. A capitalist society fundamentally depends on scarcity to function, and +so through intellectual property norms we create an artificial scarcity to +reward (and incentivize) intellectual labor without questioning our fundamental +assumptions about capitalism and value.[^subj-value] But, I digress --- let's +revisit the subject in part two. + +[^subj-value]: Another tangent on the labor theory of value seems appropriate + here. Our capitalist system is largely based on a competing theory, the + "subjective theory of value", which states that value is defined not by the + labor required to provide a product or service, but by market forces, or + more concretely by the subjective value negotiated between a buyer and + seller. I admit this theory is compelling when applied to some examples, + for example when explaining the value of a Pokemon card. When it comes to + intellectual property, however, I find it very unsatisfying, given that a + laissez-faire free market would presumably evolve a very different approach + to intellectual property. As such I think that intellectual property as a + concept depends at least a little bit on Marx for its legitimacy, which I + find very funny. + +In part two of this series on intellectual property, I will explain the modern +intellectual property regime as I understand it, as well as its history and +justification. So equipped with the philosophical and legal background, part +three will constitute the bulk of my critique of intellectual property, and my +ideals for reform. Part four will examine how these ideas altogether apply in +practice to open source, as well as the hairy questions of intellectual property +as applied to modern problems in this space, such as the use of LLMs to file the +serial numbers off of open source software. + +--- + +*If you want to dive deeper into the philosophy here, a great resource is the +Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Check out their articles on [Property and +Ownership][0] and [Redistribution][1] for a start, which expand on some of the +ideas I've drawn on here and possess a wealth of citations catalogued with a +discipline I can never seem to muster for my blog posts. I am a programmer, not +a philosopher, so if you want to learn more about this you should go read from +the hundreds of years of philosophers who have worked on this with rigor and +written down a bunch of interesting ideas.* + +[0]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/property/ +[1]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/redistribution/