logo

drewdevault.com

[mirror] blog and personal website of Drew DeVault git clone https://hacktivis.me/git/mirror/drewdevault.com.git

2025-02-13-On-intellectual-property.md (15219B)


  1. ---
  2. title: A holistic perspective on intellectual property, part 1
  3. date: 2025-02-13
  4. ---
  5. I'd like to write about intellectual property in depth, in this first of a
  6. series of blog posts on the subject. I'm not a philosopher, but philosophy is
  7. the basis of reasonable politics so buckle up for a healthy Friday afternoon
  8. serving of it.
  9. To understand intellectual property, we must first establish at least a shallow
  10. understanding of property generally. What is property?[^note] An incomplete
  11. answer might state that a material object I have power over is my property. An
  12. apple I have held in my hand is mine, insofar as nothing prevents me from using
  13. it (and, in the process, destroying it), or giving it away, or planting it in
  14. the ground. However, you might not agree that this apple is necessarily *mine*
  15. if I took it from a fruit stand without permission. This act is called "theft"
  16. --- one of many possible transgressions upon property.
  17. [^note]: In today's article I will focus mainly on personal property (e.g. your
  18. shoes), private property (e.g. a house or a business), and intellectual
  19. property (e.g. a patent or a copyright). There are other kinds: public
  20. property, collective property, and so on, but to simplify this article we
  21. will use the layman's understanding of "property" as commonly referring to
  22. personal property or private property, whichever is best supported by
  23. context, unless otherwise specified. In general terms all of these kinds of
  24. property refer to the rules with which society governs the use of *things*.
  25. It is important to note that the very possibility that one could illicitly
  26. assume possession of an object is a strong indication that "property" is a
  27. social convention, rather than a law of nature; one cannot defy the law of
  28. gravity in the same way as one can defy property. And, given that, we could try
  29. to imagine other social conventions to govern the use of *things* in a society.
  30. If we come up with an idea we like, and we're in a radical mood, we could even
  31. challenge the notion of property in society at large and seek to implement a
  32. different social convention.
  33. As it stands today, the social convention tells us property is a *thing* which
  34. has an "owner", or owners, to whom society confers certain rights with respect
  35. to the thing in question. That may include, for example, the right to use it, to
  36. destroy it, to exclude others from using it, to sell it, or give it away, and so
  37. on. Property is this special idea society uses to grant you the authority to use
  38. a bunch of verbs with respect to a thing. However, being a social convention,
  39. nothing prevents me from using any of these verbs on something society does not
  40. recognize as my property, e.g. by
  41. <abbr title='"I have a bridge to sell you" is an English-language idiom that refers to selling something you do not own to a gullible person.'>
  42. selling you this bridge</abbr>. This is why the social convention must be
  43. **enforced**.
  44. And how is it enforced? We could enforce property rights with shame: stealing
  45. can put a stain on one's reputation, and this shame may pose an impediment to
  46. one's social needs and desires, and as such theft is discouraged. We can also
  47. use guilt: if you steal something, but don't get caught, you could end up
  48. remorseful without anyone to shame you for it, particularly with respect to the
  49. harm done to the person who suffered a loss of property as a result. Ultimately,
  50. in modern society the social convention of property is enforced with, well,
  51. force. If you steal something, society has appointed someone with a gun to track
  52. you down, restrain you, and eventually lock you up in a miserable room with bars
  53. on the windows.
  54. ---
  55. *I'd like to take a moment here to acknowledge the hubris of property: we see the
  56. bounty of the natural world and impose upon it these imagined rights and
  57. privileges, divvy it up and hand it out and hoard it, and resort to cruelty if
  58. anyone steps out of line. Indeed this may be justifiable if the system of
  59. private property is sufficiently beneficial to society, and the notion of
  60. property is so deeply ingrained into our system that it feels normal and
  61. unremarkable. It's worth remembering that it has trade-offs, that we made the
  62. whole thing up, and that we can make up something else with different
  63. trade-offs. That being said, I'm personally fond of most of my personal property
  64. and I'd like to keep enjoying most of my property rights as such, so take from
  65. that what you will.*[^marx]
  66. [^marx]: Marx, among others, distinguishes between personal property and private
  67. property. The distinction is drawn in that personal property can be moved --
  68. you can pick up a T-Shirt and take it somewhere else. Private property
  69. cannot, such as land or a house. Anyway, I'm not a Marxist but I do draw
  70. from Marxist ideas for some of my analysis of intellectual property, such as
  71. the labor theory of value. We'll talk more about these ideas later on.
  72. ---
  73. One way we can justify property rights is by using them as a tool for managing
  74. *scarcity*. If demand for coffee exceeds the supply of coffee beans, a scarcity
  75. exists, meaning that not everyone who wants to have coffee gets to have some.
  76. But, we still want to enjoy scarce things. Perhaps someone who foregoes coffee
  77. will enjoy some other scarce resource, such as tea --- then everyone can benefit
  78. in some part from some access to scarce resources. I suppose that the social
  79. convention of property can derive some natural legitimacy from the fact that
  80. some resources are scarce.[^colonialism] In this sense, private property relates
  81. to the problem of distribution.
  82. [^colonialism]: It occurred to me after writing this section that the selected
  83. examples of property and scarcity as applied to coffee and tea are begging
  84. for an analysis of the subject through the lens of colonialism, but I think
  85. my readers are not quite ready for that yet.
  86. But a naive solution to distribution has flaws. For example, what of hoarding?
  87. Are property rights legitimate when someone takes more than they need or intend
  88. to use? This behavior could be motivated by an antagonistic relationship with
  89. society at large, such as as a means of driving up prices for private profit;
  90. such behavior could be considered anti-social and thus a violation of the social
  91. convention as such.
  92. Moreover, property which is destroyed by its use, such as coffee, is one matter,
  93. but further questions are raised when we consider durable goods, such as a
  94. screwdriver. The screwdriver in my shed spends the vast majority of its time out
  95. of use. Is it just for me to assert property rights over my screwdriver when I
  96. am not using it? To what extent is the scarcity of screwdrivers *necessary*?
  97. Screwdrivers are not fundamentally scarce, given that the supply of idle
  98. screwdrivers far outpaces the demand for screwdriver use, but our modern
  99. conception of property has the unintended consequence of creating scarcity where
  100. there is none by denying the use of idle screwdrivers where they are needed.
  101. Let's try to generalize our understanding of property, working our way towards
  102. "intellectual property" one step at a time. To begin with, what happens if we
  103. expand our understanding of property to include immaterial things? Consider
  104. domain names as a kind of property. In theory, domain names are abundant, but
  105. some names are more desirable than others. We assert property rights over them,
  106. in particular the right to use a name and exclude others from using it, or to
  107. derive a profit from exclusive use of a desirable name.
  108. But a domain name doesn't really exist per-se: it's just an entry in a ledger.
  109. The electric charge on the hard drives in your nearest DNS server's database
  110. exist, but the domain name it represents doesn't exist in quite the same sense
  111. as the electrons do: it's immaterial. Is applying our conception of property to
  112. these immaterial things justifiable?
  113. We can start answering this question by acknowledging that property rights are
  114. *useful* for domain names, in that this gives domain names desirable properties
  115. that serve productive ends in society. For example, exclusive control over a
  116. domain name allows a sense of authenticity to emerge from its use, so that you
  117. understand that pointing your browser to drewdevault.com will return the content
  118. that the person, Drew DeVault, wrote for you. We should also acknowledge that
  119. there are negative side-effects of asserting property rights over domains, such
  120. as domain squatting, extortionate pricing for "premium" domain names, and the
  121. advantage one party has over another if they possess a desirable name by mere
  122. fact of that possession, irrespective of merit.
  123. On the balance of things, if we concede the legitimacy of personal
  124. property[^property legitimacy] I find it relatively easy to concede the
  125. legitimacy of this sort of property, too.
  126. [^property legitimacy]: Not that I do, at least not entirely. I personally
  127. envision a system in which wealth is capped, hoarding is illegal, and
  128. everyone has an unconditional right to food, shelter, healthcare, and so on,
  129. and I'll support reforming property rights in a heartbeat if that's what it
  130. takes to get all of those things done. And, as the saying goes: if you see
  131. someone stealing groceries, you didn't see anything. My willingness to
  132. accept property as a legitimate social convention is conditional on it not
  133. producing antisocial outcomes like homelessness or food insecurity. A system
  134. like this is considered a form of "distributive justice", if you want to
  135. learn more.
  136. The next step is to consider if we can generalize property rights to govern
  137. immaterial, non-finite things, like a story. A book, its paper and bindings and
  138. ink, is a material, finite resource, and can be thought of in terms that apply
  139. to material property. But what of the words formed by the ink? They can be
  140. trivially copied with a pen and paper, or transformed into a new medium by
  141. reading it aloud to an audience, and these processes do not infringe on the
  142. material property rights associated with the book. This process cannot be
  143. thought of as stealing, as the person who possesses a copy of the book is not
  144. asserting property rights over the original. In our current intellectual
  145. property regime, this person is transgressing via use of the *idea*, the
  146. *intellectual* property --- the *thing* in the abstract space occupied by the
  147. story itself. Is that, too, a just extension of our notion of property?
  148. Imagine with me the relationship one has with one's property, independent of the
  149. social constructs around property. With respect to material property, a
  150. relationship of possession exists: I physically possess a thing, and I have the
  151. ability to make use of it through my possession of it. If someone else were to
  152. deny me access to this thing, they would have to resort to force, and I would
  153. have to resort to force should I resist their efforts.
  154. Our relationship with intellectual property is much different. An idea cannot be
  155. withheld or seized by force. Instead, our relationship to intellectual property
  156. is defined by our *history* with respect to an idea. In the case of material
  157. property, the ground truth is that I keep it locked in my home to deny others
  158. access to it, and the social construct formalizes this relationship. With
  159. respect to intellectual property, such as the story in a book, the ground truth
  160. is that, sometime in the past, I imagined it and wrote it down. The social
  161. construct of intellectual property invents an imagined relationship of
  162. possession, modelled after our relationship with material property.
  163. Why?
  164. The resource with the greatest and most fundamental scarcity is our time,[^time]
  165. and as a consequence the labor which goes into making something is of profound
  166. importance. Marx famously argued for a "labor theory of value", which tells us
  167. that the value inherent in a good or service is in the labor which is required
  168. to provide it. I think he was on to something![^marx 2] Intellectual property is
  169. not scarce, nor can it be possessed, but it does have *value*, and that value
  170. could ultimately be derived from the labor which produced it.
  171. [^time]: And you're spending some of it to read my silly blog, which I really
  172. feel is an honor. Thank you.
  173. [^marx 2]: Marx loses me at historical determinism and the dominance of man over
  174. nature through dogmatic industrialization, among other things, but the labor
  175. theory of value is good shit.
  176. The social justification for intellectual property as a legal concept is rooted
  177. in the value of this labor. We recognize that intellectual labor is valuable,
  178. and produces an artifact --- e.g. a story --- which is valuable, but is not
  179. scarce. A capitalist society fundamentally depends on scarcity to function, and
  180. so through intellectual property norms we create an artificial scarcity to
  181. reward (and incentivize) intellectual labor without questioning our fundamental
  182. assumptions about capitalism and value.[^subj-value] But, I digress --- let's
  183. revisit the subject in part two.
  184. [^subj-value]: Another tangent on the labor theory of value seems appropriate
  185. here. Our capitalist system is largely based on a competing theory, the
  186. "subjective theory of value", which states that value is defined not by the
  187. labor required to provide a product or service, but by market forces, or
  188. more concretely by the subjective value negotiated between a buyer and
  189. seller. I admit this theory is compelling when applied to some examples,
  190. for example when explaining the value of a Pokemon card. When it comes to
  191. intellectual property, however, I find it very unsatisfying, given that a
  192. laissez-faire free market would presumably evolve a very different approach
  193. to intellectual property. As such I think that intellectual property as a
  194. concept depends at least a little bit on Marx for its legitimacy, which I
  195. find very funny.
  196. In part two of this series on intellectual property, I will explain the modern
  197. intellectual property regime as I understand it, as well as its history and
  198. justification. So equipped with the philosophical and legal background, part
  199. three will constitute the bulk of my critique of intellectual property, and my
  200. ideals for reform. Part four will examine how these ideas altogether apply in
  201. practice to open source, as well as the hairy questions of intellectual property
  202. as applied to modern problems in this space, such as the use of LLMs to file the
  203. serial numbers off of open source software.
  204. ---
  205. *If you want to dive deeper into the philosophy here, a great resource is the
  206. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Check out their articles on [Property and
  207. Ownership][0] and [Redistribution][1] for a start, which expand on some of the
  208. ideas I've drawn on here and possess a wealth of citations catalogued with a
  209. discipline I can never seem to muster for my blog posts. I am a programmer, not
  210. a philosopher, so if you want to learn more about this you should go read from
  211. the hundreds of years of philosophers who have worked on this with rigor and
  212. written down a bunch of interesting ideas.*
  213. [0]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/property/
  214. [1]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/redistribution/