2025-02-13-On-intellectual-property.md (15219B)
- ---
- title: A holistic perspective on intellectual property, part 1
- date: 2025-02-13
- ---
- I'd like to write about intellectual property in depth, in this first of a
- series of blog posts on the subject. I'm not a philosopher, but philosophy is
- the basis of reasonable politics so buckle up for a healthy Friday afternoon
- serving of it.
- To understand intellectual property, we must first establish at least a shallow
- understanding of property generally. What is property?[^note] An incomplete
- answer might state that a material object I have power over is my property. An
- apple I have held in my hand is mine, insofar as nothing prevents me from using
- it (and, in the process, destroying it), or giving it away, or planting it in
- the ground. However, you might not agree that this apple is necessarily *mine*
- if I took it from a fruit stand without permission. This act is called "theft"
- --- one of many possible transgressions upon property.
- [^note]: In today's article I will focus mainly on personal property (e.g. your
- shoes), private property (e.g. a house or a business), and intellectual
- property (e.g. a patent or a copyright). There are other kinds: public
- property, collective property, and so on, but to simplify this article we
- will use the layman's understanding of "property" as commonly referring to
- personal property or private property, whichever is best supported by
- context, unless otherwise specified. In general terms all of these kinds of
- property refer to the rules with which society governs the use of *things*.
- It is important to note that the very possibility that one could illicitly
- assume possession of an object is a strong indication that "property" is a
- social convention, rather than a law of nature; one cannot defy the law of
- gravity in the same way as one can defy property. And, given that, we could try
- to imagine other social conventions to govern the use of *things* in a society.
- If we come up with an idea we like, and we're in a radical mood, we could even
- challenge the notion of property in society at large and seek to implement a
- different social convention.
- As it stands today, the social convention tells us property is a *thing* which
- has an "owner", or owners, to whom society confers certain rights with respect
- to the thing in question. That may include, for example, the right to use it, to
- destroy it, to exclude others from using it, to sell it, or give it away, and so
- on. Property is this special idea society uses to grant you the authority to use
- a bunch of verbs with respect to a thing. However, being a social convention,
- nothing prevents me from using any of these verbs on something society does not
- recognize as my property, e.g. by
- <abbr title='"I have a bridge to sell you" is an English-language idiom that refers to selling something you do not own to a gullible person.'>
- selling you this bridge</abbr>. This is why the social convention must be
- **enforced**.
- And how is it enforced? We could enforce property rights with shame: stealing
- can put a stain on one's reputation, and this shame may pose an impediment to
- one's social needs and desires, and as such theft is discouraged. We can also
- use guilt: if you steal something, but don't get caught, you could end up
- remorseful without anyone to shame you for it, particularly with respect to the
- harm done to the person who suffered a loss of property as a result. Ultimately,
- in modern society the social convention of property is enforced with, well,
- force. If you steal something, society has appointed someone with a gun to track
- you down, restrain you, and eventually lock you up in a miserable room with bars
- on the windows.
- ---
- *I'd like to take a moment here to acknowledge the hubris of property: we see the
- bounty of the natural world and impose upon it these imagined rights and
- privileges, divvy it up and hand it out and hoard it, and resort to cruelty if
- anyone steps out of line. Indeed this may be justifiable if the system of
- private property is sufficiently beneficial to society, and the notion of
- property is so deeply ingrained into our system that it feels normal and
- unremarkable. It's worth remembering that it has trade-offs, that we made the
- whole thing up, and that we can make up something else with different
- trade-offs. That being said, I'm personally fond of most of my personal property
- and I'd like to keep enjoying most of my property rights as such, so take from
- that what you will.*[^marx]
- [^marx]: Marx, among others, distinguishes between personal property and private
- property. The distinction is drawn in that personal property can be moved --
- you can pick up a T-Shirt and take it somewhere else. Private property
- cannot, such as land or a house. Anyway, I'm not a Marxist but I do draw
- from Marxist ideas for some of my analysis of intellectual property, such as
- the labor theory of value. We'll talk more about these ideas later on.
- ---
- One way we can justify property rights is by using them as a tool for managing
- *scarcity*. If demand for coffee exceeds the supply of coffee beans, a scarcity
- exists, meaning that not everyone who wants to have coffee gets to have some.
- But, we still want to enjoy scarce things. Perhaps someone who foregoes coffee
- will enjoy some other scarce resource, such as tea --- then everyone can benefit
- in some part from some access to scarce resources. I suppose that the social
- convention of property can derive some natural legitimacy from the fact that
- some resources are scarce.[^colonialism] In this sense, private property relates
- to the problem of distribution.
- [^colonialism]: It occurred to me after writing this section that the selected
- examples of property and scarcity as applied to coffee and tea are begging
- for an analysis of the subject through the lens of colonialism, but I think
- my readers are not quite ready for that yet.
- But a naive solution to distribution has flaws. For example, what of hoarding?
- Are property rights legitimate when someone takes more than they need or intend
- to use? This behavior could be motivated by an antagonistic relationship with
- society at large, such as as a means of driving up prices for private profit;
- such behavior could be considered anti-social and thus a violation of the social
- convention as such.
- Moreover, property which is destroyed by its use, such as coffee, is one matter,
- but further questions are raised when we consider durable goods, such as a
- screwdriver. The screwdriver in my shed spends the vast majority of its time out
- of use. Is it just for me to assert property rights over my screwdriver when I
- am not using it? To what extent is the scarcity of screwdrivers *necessary*?
- Screwdrivers are not fundamentally scarce, given that the supply of idle
- screwdrivers far outpaces the demand for screwdriver use, but our modern
- conception of property has the unintended consequence of creating scarcity where
- there is none by denying the use of idle screwdrivers where they are needed.
- Let's try to generalize our understanding of property, working our way towards
- "intellectual property" one step at a time. To begin with, what happens if we
- expand our understanding of property to include immaterial things? Consider
- domain names as a kind of property. In theory, domain names are abundant, but
- some names are more desirable than others. We assert property rights over them,
- in particular the right to use a name and exclude others from using it, or to
- derive a profit from exclusive use of a desirable name.
- But a domain name doesn't really exist per-se: it's just an entry in a ledger.
- The electric charge on the hard drives in your nearest DNS server's database
- exist, but the domain name it represents doesn't exist in quite the same sense
- as the electrons do: it's immaterial. Is applying our conception of property to
- these immaterial things justifiable?
- We can start answering this question by acknowledging that property rights are
- *useful* for domain names, in that this gives domain names desirable properties
- that serve productive ends in society. For example, exclusive control over a
- domain name allows a sense of authenticity to emerge from its use, so that you
- understand that pointing your browser to drewdevault.com will return the content
- that the person, Drew DeVault, wrote for you. We should also acknowledge that
- there are negative side-effects of asserting property rights over domains, such
- as domain squatting, extortionate pricing for "premium" domain names, and the
- advantage one party has over another if they possess a desirable name by mere
- fact of that possession, irrespective of merit.
- On the balance of things, if we concede the legitimacy of personal
- property[^property legitimacy] I find it relatively easy to concede the
- legitimacy of this sort of property, too.
- [^property legitimacy]: Not that I do, at least not entirely. I personally
- envision a system in which wealth is capped, hoarding is illegal, and
- everyone has an unconditional right to food, shelter, healthcare, and so on,
- and I'll support reforming property rights in a heartbeat if that's what it
- takes to get all of those things done. And, as the saying goes: if you see
- someone stealing groceries, you didn't see anything. My willingness to
- accept property as a legitimate social convention is conditional on it not
- producing antisocial outcomes like homelessness or food insecurity. A system
- like this is considered a form of "distributive justice", if you want to
- learn more.
- The next step is to consider if we can generalize property rights to govern
- immaterial, non-finite things, like a story. A book, its paper and bindings and
- ink, is a material, finite resource, and can be thought of in terms that apply
- to material property. But what of the words formed by the ink? They can be
- trivially copied with a pen and paper, or transformed into a new medium by
- reading it aloud to an audience, and these processes do not infringe on the
- material property rights associated with the book. This process cannot be
- thought of as stealing, as the person who possesses a copy of the book is not
- asserting property rights over the original. In our current intellectual
- property regime, this person is transgressing via use of the *idea*, the
- *intellectual* property --- the *thing* in the abstract space occupied by the
- story itself. Is that, too, a just extension of our notion of property?
- Imagine with me the relationship one has with one's property, independent of the
- social constructs around property. With respect to material property, a
- relationship of possession exists: I physically possess a thing, and I have the
- ability to make use of it through my possession of it. If someone else were to
- deny me access to this thing, they would have to resort to force, and I would
- have to resort to force should I resist their efforts.
- Our relationship with intellectual property is much different. An idea cannot be
- withheld or seized by force. Instead, our relationship to intellectual property
- is defined by our *history* with respect to an idea. In the case of material
- property, the ground truth is that I keep it locked in my home to deny others
- access to it, and the social construct formalizes this relationship. With
- respect to intellectual property, such as the story in a book, the ground truth
- is that, sometime in the past, I imagined it and wrote it down. The social
- construct of intellectual property invents an imagined relationship of
- possession, modelled after our relationship with material property.
- Why?
- The resource with the greatest and most fundamental scarcity is our time,[^time]
- and as a consequence the labor which goes into making something is of profound
- importance. Marx famously argued for a "labor theory of value", which tells us
- that the value inherent in a good or service is in the labor which is required
- to provide it. I think he was on to something![^marx 2] Intellectual property is
- not scarce, nor can it be possessed, but it does have *value*, and that value
- could ultimately be derived from the labor which produced it.
- [^time]: And you're spending some of it to read my silly blog, which I really
- feel is an honor. Thank you.
- [^marx 2]: Marx loses me at historical determinism and the dominance of man over
- nature through dogmatic industrialization, among other things, but the labor
- theory of value is good shit.
- The social justification for intellectual property as a legal concept is rooted
- in the value of this labor. We recognize that intellectual labor is valuable,
- and produces an artifact --- e.g. a story --- which is valuable, but is not
- scarce. A capitalist society fundamentally depends on scarcity to function, and
- so through intellectual property norms we create an artificial scarcity to
- reward (and incentivize) intellectual labor without questioning our fundamental
- assumptions about capitalism and value.[^subj-value] But, I digress --- let's
- revisit the subject in part two.
- [^subj-value]: Another tangent on the labor theory of value seems appropriate
- here. Our capitalist system is largely based on a competing theory, the
- "subjective theory of value", which states that value is defined not by the
- labor required to provide a product or service, but by market forces, or
- more concretely by the subjective value negotiated between a buyer and
- seller. I admit this theory is compelling when applied to some examples,
- for example when explaining the value of a Pokemon card. When it comes to
- intellectual property, however, I find it very unsatisfying, given that a
- laissez-faire free market would presumably evolve a very different approach
- to intellectual property. As such I think that intellectual property as a
- concept depends at least a little bit on Marx for its legitimacy, which I
- find very funny.
- In part two of this series on intellectual property, I will explain the modern
- intellectual property regime as I understand it, as well as its history and
- justification. So equipped with the philosophical and legal background, part
- three will constitute the bulk of my critique of intellectual property, and my
- ideals for reform. Part four will examine how these ideas altogether apply in
- practice to open source, as well as the hairy questions of intellectual property
- as applied to modern problems in this space, such as the use of LLMs to file the
- serial numbers off of open source software.
- ---
- *If you want to dive deeper into the philosophy here, a great resource is the
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Check out their articles on [Property and
- Ownership][0] and [Redistribution][1] for a start, which expand on some of the
- ideas I've drawn on here and possess a wealth of citations catalogued with a
- discipline I can never seem to muster for my blog posts. I am a programmer, not
- a philosopher, so if you want to learn more about this you should go read from
- the hundreds of years of philosophers who have worked on this with rigor and
- written down a bunch of interesting ideas.*
- [0]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/property/
- [1]: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/redistribution/